In computational complexity theory, an alternating Turing machine (ATM) is a non-deterministic Turing machine (NTM) with a rule for accepting computations that generalizes the rules used in the definition of the complexity classes NP and co-NP. The concept of an ATM was set forth by Chandra and Stockmeyer in 1976 (see References).
Contents |
The definition of NP uses the existential mode of computation: if any choice leads to an accepting state, then the whole computation accepts. The definition of co-NP uses the universal mode of computation: only if all choices lead to an accepting state, then the whole computation accepts. An alternating Turing machine (or to be more precise, the definition of acceptance for such a machine) alternates between these modes.
An alternating Turing machine is a non-deterministic Turing machine whose states are divided into two sets: existential states and universal states. An existential state is accepting if some transition leads to an accepting state; a universal state is accepting if every transition leads to an accepting state. (Thus a universal state with no transitions accepts unconditionally; an existential state with no transitions rejects unconditionally). The machine as a whole accepts if the initial state is accepting.
Formally, a (one-tape) alternating Turing machine is a 5-tuple where
If M is in a state with then that configuration is said to be accepting, and if the configuration is said to be rejecting. A configuration with is said to be accepting if all configurations reachable in one step are accepting, and rejecting if some configuration reachable in one step is rejecting. A configuration with is said to be accepting when there exists some configuration reachable in one step which is accepting and rejecting when all configurations reachable in one step are rejecting (this is the type of all states in an NTM). M is said to accept an input string w if the initial configuration of M (the state of M is , the head is at the left end of the tape, and the tape contains w) is accepting, and to reject if the initial configuration is rejecting.
When deciding if a configuration of an ATM is accepting or rejecting using the above definition, it is not necessary to examine all configurations reachable from the current configuration. In particular, an existential configuration can be labelled as accepting if any successor configuration is found to be accepting, and a universal configuration can be labelled as rejecting if any successor configuration is found to be rejecting.
An ATM decides a formal language in time if, on any input of length , examining configurations only up to steps is sufficient to label the initial configuration as accepting or rejecting. An ATM decides a language in space if examining configurations which do not modify tape cells beyond the cell from the left is sufficient.
A language which is decided by some ATM in time for some constant is said to be in the class , and a language decided in space is said to be in the class .
Perhaps the simplest problem for alternating machines to solve is the quantified boolean formula problem, which is a generalization of the boolean satisfiability problem in which each variable can be bound by either an existential or a universal quantifier. The alternating machine branches existentially to try all possible values of an existentially quantified variable and universally to try all possible values of a universally quantified variable, in the left-to-right order in which they are bound. After deciding a value for all quantified variables, the machine accepts or rejects according as the resulting boolean formula evaluates to true or false. Thus at an existentially quantified variable the machine is accepting if a value can be substituted for the variable which renders the remaining problem satisfiable, and at a universally quantified variable the machine is accepting if any value can be substituted and the remaining problem is satisfiable.
Such a machine decides quantified boolean formulas in time and space .
The boolean satisfiability problem can be viewed as the special case where all variables are existentially quantified, allowing ordinary nondeterminism, which uses only existential branching, to solve it efficiently.
The following complexity classes are useful to define for ATMs:
These are similar to the definitions of P, PSPACE, and EXPTIME, considering the resources used by an ATM rather than a deterministic Turing machine. Chandra, Kozen, and Stockmeyer proved the theorems
When and This is expressed by the Parallel computation thesis.
An alternating Turing machine with k alternations is an alternating Turing machine which switches from an existential to a universal state or vice versa no more than k−1 times. (It is an alternating Turing machine whose states are divided into k sets. The states in even-numbered sets are universal and the states in odd-numbered sets are existential (or vice versa). The machine has no transitions between a state in set i and a state in set j < i.)
is the class of function in time beginning by existential state and alternating at most times. It is called the th level of the hierarchy.
is the same classes, but beginning by a universal state, it is the complement of the language of .
is defined similarly for space bounded computation.
Consider the circuit minimization problem: given a circuit A computing a Boolean function f and a number n, determine if there is a circuit with at most n gates that computes the same function f. An alternating Turing machine, with one alternation, starting in an existential state, can solve this problem in polynomial time (by guessing a circuit B with at most n gates, then switching to a universal state, guessing an input, and checking that the output of B on that input matches the output of A on that input).
It is said that a hierarchy collapse to level if every language in level of a hierarchy is in its level .
As a corollary of Immerman–Szelepcsényi theorem, the logarithm space hierarchy collapse to its first level.[1] As a corollary the hierarchy collapse to the first level when is space constructible.
An alternating Turing machine in polynomial time with k alternations, starting in an existential (respectively, universal) state can decide all the problems in the class (respectively, ). See the polynomial hierarchy article.
Another special case of time hierarchies is the logarithmic hierarchy.